@Blotty
Regarding dia
in Romans 11:36, your claim that it refers to "source" rather than
"channel" misunderstands the distinction between the prepositions ex
(from) and dia (through). Paul uses ex for the Father as the
ultimate source ("from Him") and dia for the Son as the
means or agent ("through Him"). This distinction highlights
relational roles within the Godhead rather than ontological subordination. Dia
consistently denotes agency rather than origination in the Pauline corpus when
applied to Christ (e.g., John 1:3, Colossians 1:16, Hebrews 1:2). Your
interpretation conflates these relational nuances, undermining the Trinitarian
understanding of shared divine essence and distinct personal roles.
The claim that in Romans
11:36, dia refers to God as the source rather than as a channel
misunderstands the preposition's semantic range and the specific context of this
passage. In Romans 11:36, Paul uses three prepositional phrases: "from
Him" (ex autou), "through Him" (dia autou),
and "to Him" (eis auton). These prepositions highlight
distinct aspects of God's relationship to creation: ex autou indicates
that God is the ultimate source, dia autou emphasizes His active
agency or means, and eis auton denotes the goal or purpose. The use of
dia in this context does not imply inferiority but underscores the
unity of the Godhead in creation. In Johannine theology, dia similarly
reflects Christ’s active role in creation as the divine Word, not a subordinate
instrument, but one who fully participates in the work of creation as God.
Your question about a
"passive instrument" reveals a misunderstanding of the term and the
argument. A passive instrument would imply something used by another without
agency or self-determination, akin to a tool wielded by a craftsman. However,
John 1:3 explicitly negates this interpretation by stating that "all
things were made through Him, and without Him was not anything made that was
made." This clause establishes the Logos as the necessary and active agent
of creation. The Logos is not passive but integral to the creative process, as
indicated by the phrase "without Him" (choris autou), which
excludes any possibility of creation occurring apart from Him. This absolute
negation leaves no room for the Logos to be a mere instrument or created being.
The idea that
"absolute negation" was idiomatic in the biblical era lacks textual
evidence in this context. While hyperbolic or idiomatic language exists in
Scripture, the construction in John 1:3 is precise and unambiguous. The use of choris
autou—combined with the double negation in the Greek text ("without
Him was not... anything that was made")—intensifies the exclusivity of the
Logos's role in creation. This language rules out the notion that the Logos is
part of creation or a secondary agent.
Your assertion that Christ
could be both "created" and "uncreated," drawing on Philo's
concept of the Logos, reflects a misunderstanding of both Philo's philosophy
and John's theology. Philo's Logos is a philosophical abstraction, a mediator
between the divine and the material, whereas John's Logos is a person—Jesus
Christ—who is fully divine and eternal. John’s description of the Logos as
"with God" (pros ton Theon) and "was God" (theos
ēn ho logos) affirms the Logos's full divinity and eternal existence.
Unlike Eve, who was derived from Adam and is ontologically subordinate to him,
the Logos is of the same divine essence as the Father, as clarified by the
Nicene Creed's term homoousios ("of the same substance").
The analogy you propose is therefore incompatible with Johannine and Nicene
theology. Philo's Logos
concept is philosophical speculation, while John's Logos is firmly grounded in
Jewish monotheism and the revelation of Christ as fully divine. The Logos is
not created "from God's substance" in the manner you describe; such a
view parallels Arianism, which was condemned as heretical by the early Church.
The Nicene Creed clarifies that the Son is "begotten, not made,
consubstantial with the Father." The analogy of Eve being formed from Adam
misunderstands the distinction between human derivation and divine begetting.
The Son's "begetting" is eternal, not a temporal or contingent event,
emphasizing His equality and consubstantiality with the Father.
Your claim that creation is
attributed solely to the Father reflects a selective reading of the Church
Fathers. While the Father is often described as the "source" of
creation (ex ou), the Son is consistently portrayed as the agent (dia
hou), and the Spirit as the perfecting force. This Trinitarian framework
is evident in Scripture (e.g., John 1:3, Col. 1:16-17, Heb. 1:2, 1 Cor. 8:6)
and upheld by patristic theology. For instance, Irenaeus, in Against
Heresies (Book 4, Chapter 20), refers to the Son and Spirit as the
"two hands of God" in creation. This imagery underscores the
collaborative and unified work of the Trinity in creation, without suggesting
any ontological hierarchy.
Regarding Daniel Wallace
and A.T. Robertson, your citations do not contradict my argument but rather
reinforce it. Both scholars affirm that dia in John 1:3 and Colossians
1:16 emphasizes the Logos’s role as the divine agent in creation. Wallace, in Greek
Grammar Beyond the Basics, explains that dia can indicate agency
without implying inferiority, particularly when the context involves divine
action. Similarly, Robertson acknowledges that the Son functions as the
"intermediate agent" in creation, which is consistent with
Trinitarian theology. Your attempt to use these scholars to suggest
subordination misrepresents their positions, as neither Wallace nor Robertson
denies the Logos’s full divinity or eternal nature. So your citation of Daniel
Wallace and A.T. Robertson supports my argument, not yours. Wallace explicitly
identifies dia as indicative of agency in John 1:3 and Colossians
1:16, emphasizing the Son's role in creation without implying inferiority.
Robertson similarly recognizes the Logos as the active, sustaining agent in
creation. Your selective interpretation of their works misrepresents their
conclusions, which consistently affirm the high Christology of these texts.
The appeal to the
intermediate agency of the Logos as a basis for subordination is a category
error. In Trinitarian theology, "agency" reflects the relational
distinctions within the Godhead, not an ontological hierarchy. The Father, Son,
and Spirit act inseparably in all divine works, including creation. The Son’s
role as the agent of creation (dia hou) does not imply subordination
but highlights the relational economy of the Trinity, where the Father is the
source, the Son the agent, and the Spirit the perfecter.
Your interpretation of the
Logos as "created from God’s substance" contradicts the biblical and
theological witness. The Nicene Creed explicitly rejects the idea that the Son
is "made" (poiētos), affirming instead that He is
"begotten, not made" (gennētos, ou poiētos). This
distinction underscores that the Son is eternally generated from the Father,
sharing the same divine essence, rather than being a creation. The analogy of
Eve's derivation from Adam fails to capture the eternal and consubstantial
relationship between the Father and the Son, which is foundational to
Trinitarian theology.
On your point that the
Church Fathers attribute creation solely to the Father, this is inaccurate.
While the Fathers emphasize the Father's role as the source of creation, they
also affirm the Son's active participation as Creator. For example, Irenaeus
states in Against Heresies (Book 2, Chapter 30): "The Father,
indeed, is above all, and He is the Head of Christ; but the Word is through all
things and is Himself the head of the Church." This statement aligns with
Hebrews 1:2 and Colossians 1:16, where the Son is described as the agent of
creation. The relational distinctions in these descriptions reflect the
economic Trinity, not subordination.
Regarding BeDuhn, his
acknowledgment of theos as qualitative does not negate Christ's
divinity. While BeDuhn prefers "divine" as a translation, he
recognizes that this aligns with the Logos's divine nature as described in John
1:1. The qualitative use of theos emphasizes the Logos's full
participation in the divine essence, not a lesser or created status. Your claim
that I selectively omitted information is unsubstantiated; BeDuhn’s linguistic
analysis supports the traditional understanding of John 1:1 as affirming the
Logos's divine nature, even if he does not personally endorse Trinitarian
theology.
BeDuhn acknowledges that theos
can denote a category or class, but he does not reduce the Logos to being
merely "a god" in the sense of polytheism or henotheism. Instead, his
preference for the term "divine" reflects the qualitative nature of theos
in John 1:1c, aligning with the broader Johannine context that emphasizes the
Word's intrinsic divinity. This interpretation does not equate to an
endorsement of the JWs’ theological stance, as BeDuhn himself critiques their
translation's theological bias elsewhere.
Regarding the claim that theos
as a "count noun" undermines its qualitative force, this argument misunderstands
Greek syntax and semantics. While theos can function as a count noun,
its role in John 1:1c aligns with qualitative usage. As noted by Harner and
other scholars, the anarthrous predicate noun preceding the verb often
emphasizes the nature or essence of the subject. In this case, it attributes
divinity to the Word, consistent with the Gospel's prologue and broader
theological framework. The qualitative interpretation of theos here
does not necessitate subordination or categorical division but underscores the
Word's shared essence with God. Check these:
The criticism that the
neuter hen in John 10:30 does not indicate unity of essence due to the
Incarnation is also misplaced. Theological nuances of Christ's dual nature
(divine and human) do not negate His ontological unity with the Father. The use
of hen emphasizes unity of will and essence, not mere functional
agreement. This is corroborated by the immediate context, where Jesus’ claim
leads to accusations of blasphemy, indicating that His audience understood Him
to assert divine identity, not merely cooperative action.
On the claim that God as
"spirit" (John 4:24) precludes Jesus’ shared essence during His
earthly ministry, this reflects a misunderstanding of Trinitarian theology. The
Incarnation does not diminish or alter Christ's divine essence; rather, it
affirms the hypostatic union, where Christ is fully God and fully man.
Describing God as "spirit" emphasizes His immaterial and eternal
nature, which Jesus shares as the Logos.
The appeal to theos
as a "count noun" fails to refute its qualitative application in John
1:1c. The argument presupposes a rigid linguistic framework that dismisses
established grammatical insights. Scholars like Wallace and Harner demonstrate
that theos in this context functions to attribute the essence of
divinity to the Word without implying numerical separation or inferiority. The
argument that theos must always be definite or indefinite overlooks
the nuanced qualitative category evident in Koine Greek.
The critique conflates
BeDuhn’s linguistic analysis with theological conclusions he does not make. His
acknowledgment of the grammatical possibility of “a god” does not mean he
endorses it as the most accurate or contextually appropriate rendering.
BeDuhn’s focus on qualitative nuance supports a reading that recognizes the
Word’s divinity in harmony with monotheistic Jewish theology. Mischaracterizing
his position as aligning with JW theology misrepresents his work and the
broader academic consensus.
Your assertion that ego
eimi in John 8:58 simply indicates existence before Abraham but
not eternal existence fails to account for the linguistic and contextual
factors. The phrase ego eimi (I am) is not merely a statement of past
existence but a present-tense declaration of ongoing being. This present tense,
coupled with the temporal clause prin Abraam genesthai (“before
Abraham came to be”), creates a contrast that goes beyond the simple claim of
existence at a specific point in time. The use of the present tense where a
past tense (e.g., ēmēn, “I was”) might be expected indicates a
timeless, ongoing existence. This is consistent with how John presents
Jesus in the Prologue (John 1:1), where the Logos is described as
eternally pre-existent and divine.
Your suggestion that
eternal existence could have been conveyed another way ignores the flexibility
of Greek grammar. The structure of ego eimi uniquely emphasizes
existence in a way that transcends time, which is precisely what John intended
to communicate. It aligns with the Prologue's declaration that “the Word was
with God, and the Word was God” and reflects a deliberate theological choice to
present Jesus as the eternal Logos.
The dismissal of the
connection between ego eimi in John 8:58 and the divine name
in Exodus 3:14 is unfounded. While it is true that the LXX renders Exodus
3:14 as ego eimi ho on (“I am the Being”), the theological
resonance between the two passages cannot be ignored. The use of ego eimi
in John 8:58, without the qualification of ho on, emphasizes
the immediacy and simplicity of Jesus’ claim to divinity. The reaction of the
Jews—attempting to stone Him—confirms that they understood this as a
blasphemous assertion of deity, paralleling God’s self-revelation to Moses. The
assertion that ego eimi in John 8:58 carries the same
resonance as ho on in Exodus 3:14 is supported by the broader
Johannine context. The use of ego eimi in John consistently
affirms Jesus’ divine identity, as seen in statements like “I am the way, the
truth, and the life” (John 14:6) and “I am the resurrection and the
life” (John 11:25). These declarations align with the divine
self-revelation in Exodus and reflect Jesus’ unique role in salvation
history.
The argument that ho on
is emphasized in Exodus 3:14 rather than ego eimi overlooks
the broader significance of God’s self-identification. While the phrase ho
on (“the Being”) is present, ego eimi remains integral to the
passage’s theology as it introduces God’s eternal and self-sufficient
existence. The absence of ho on in John 8:58 does not diminish
the theological connection but reflects John’s focus on Jesus’ appropriation of
the divine name. The Gospel of John consistently portrays Jesus as embodying
the divine identity, as seen in His other “I am” statements (e.g., John
6:35, John 14:6).
The claim that the Jews’
reaction was merely “perceived blasphemy” does not weaken the argument.
Throughout the Gospel of John, the Jewish leaders accuse Jesus of blasphemy
specifically because He claims equality with God (John 5:18; 10:30-33). The
stoning attempt in John 8:59 is consistent with their understanding
that Jesus was asserting divinity, whether or not they accepted the claim.
Your argument regarding the
question “Who are you?” (John 8:25) as evidence that the Jews did not
initially understand ego eimi as a divine claim overlooks the
developing narrative. The question reflects their confusion and resistance to
Jesus’ identity, not a denial of His claims. By the time of John 8:58-59,
their reaction indicates that they did understand the theological weight of His
words, even if they rejected the claim.
The idea that ego eimi
could have been expressed differently to imply eternality misunderstands the
nuance of Greek grammar. Using a past-tense verb like ēmēn (“I was”)
would imply that Jesus’ existence before Abraham was finite or had ceased,
which contradicts the intended meaning. The choice of the present tense conveys
a continuous and timeless existence, aligning with the divine
self-identification in Exodus 3:14.
Your argument that “Son of
God” implies equality with God but not divinity in Jewish thought
oversimplifies the theological context. While it is true that Son of God
could be used for righteous individuals or the Davidic king, Jesus’ usage
consistently goes beyond this. In John 5:18, the Jews understand His
claim as making Himself “equal with God,” which they consider blasphemy. This
equality is not merely functional but ontological, as evidenced by Jesus’
further claims of unity with the Father (John 10:30) and His acceptance of
divine worship (John 20:28).
Your dismissal of the
predicate-less ego eimi in John 8:58 as an echo of Exodus 3:14 ignores
both the linguistic and theological context. The Septuagint's rendering of
Exodus 3:14 as ego eimi ho on ("I am the Being") establishes
a connection between ego eimi and divine self-identification. In John
8:58, Jesus deliberately uses ego eimi in a way that transcends
temporal constraints, asserting eternal existence. The Jews'
reaction—attempting to stone Him—demonstrates their understanding of His claim
to deity, consistent with the Gospel's high Christology. The suggestion of an
implied predicate in ego eimi based on the NIV translation does not
apply to John 8:58. While ego eimi can have an implied
predicate in some contexts (e.g., John 6:20, “It is I”), its predicate-less
usage in John 8:58 is unique and intentional. It conveys existence
rather than identification, reinforcing its theological significance.
Your argument that the
Jews' initial question, "Who are you?" (John 8:25), undermines the
divine claim of ego eimi in John 8:58 is flawed. The question reflects
their ongoing misunderstanding and resistance to Jesus' identity, a recurring
theme in John's Gospel. By the time of John 8:58, the context and phrasing of
Jesus' statement clearly provoke the Jews to accuse Him of blasphemy,
confirming their recognition of His divine claim. The claim that the Jewish
reaction in John 8:59 could be explained solely by Jesus’ claim to have
seen Abraham is inadequate. While the statement that Jesus existed before
Abraham would be provocative, it would not necessarily provoke an accusation of
blasphemy and an immediate attempt to stone Him. The context and reaction
suggest that the Jews understood Jesus’ words as a claim to divine identity.
On John 5:18, your
assertion that the Jews accused Jesus only of equality with God, not being God,
misreads the text. Equality with God in this context implies sharing divine
prerogatives, which the Jews understood as a claim to deity. Similarly, your
claim that the Son's authority to forgive sins (Mark 2:10) was merely given to
Him ignores the broader theological context of His divine identity. The
authority to forgive sins is a prerogative of God alone (Isaiah 43:25), and
Jesus exercises it by His own inherent authority.
Your argument that Jesus’
authority to forgive sins was merely given to Him (e.g., Mark 2:10)
misunderstands the theological implications. While Jesus acts in accordance
with the Father’s will, His authority to forgive sins reflects His divine
identity. The scribes’ reaction in Mark 2:7 (“Who can forgive sins but God
alone?”) confirms that they understood this act as a claim to divine
prerogative. The argument that the Jews only accused Jesus of claiming equality
with God but not of being God misrepresents the text. In John 10:33,
the Jews explicitly accuse Jesus of “making [Himself] God,” demonstrating that
they understood His claim to be ontological, not merely functional. The
distinction you propose between equality and identity does not hold in the
context of the Jewish leaders’ accusations.
Your critique of
Revelation's use of "Alpha and Omega" fails to account for the
consistent application of this title to Christ (Revelation 1:8, 21:6, 22:13),
affirming His divine status. While the title also applies to the Father, this
reflects the shared divine identity of the Father and the Son, consistent with
Trinitarian theology.
Trinitarian theology, as you rightly pointed out, is derived from the cumulative
and interconnected evidence of Scripture, not isolated passages. This
approach respects the nature of biblical revelation, where truths about God are
revealed progressively and holistically across the entirety of Scripture. In
contrast, JW theology is built on such one-liner prooftexts and punchlines, and
it is entirely fair to point out that this does not actually work.
The reason Trinitarians ask JWs for explicit passages—such as evidence that
Jesus is Michael the Archangel—is because the JW position hinges on claims
of explicit textual evidence. For example, they assert that Jesus is
explicitly Michael, or that God’s name "Jehovah" must appear in the NT,
and so the burden of proof naturally falls on them to provide direct support
for those assertions.
By contrast, Trinitarian theology doesn’t rest on one isolated verse but on
the whole counsel of Scripture. For example:
- John 1:1 describes the divine nature of the
Logos, who "was God."
- Philippians 2:6 speaks of Christ’s equality with
God.
- Matthew 28:19 demonstrates the unity and shared
authority of the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit.
These passages, taken together with others like John 20:28 (where Thomas
calls Jesus "My Lord and My God") and Colossians 1:15–20 (describing
Christ as the Creator of all things), form a cohesive picture that supports the
Trinity.
When JWs or other non-Trinitarians challenge the Trinity, they often focus
on denying its cumulative basis, insisting instead on isolated, explicit texts
that they feel undermine it. Yet, when challenged on their own teachings (e.g.,
that Jesus is Michael), they cannot provide cumulative evidence—let alone
explicit texts—to substantiate their position.
Thus, the request for explicit passages is not a double standard; it’s a
logical response to specific claims. Trinitarian doctrine has never claimed to
rest on a single verse but on the consistent and harmonious testimony of
Scripture as a whole. I would encourage you to apply the same standard of
cumulative evidence to your own theology and ask whether it aligns with the
breadth of biblical revelation.